FOR MORE OF THIS COURSE AND ANY OTHER COURSES, TEST
BANKS, FINAL EXAMS, AND SOLUTION MANUALS
CONTACT US
1.
Epistemology is the branch of philosophy concerned primarily with the nature, sources, limits, and criteria of knowledge. In the history of philosophy, epistemology and metaphysics have been intimately connected.
2.
“Metaphysics,” the term,
in its original meaning refers to
those untitled writings of Aristotle “after the Physics” that deal with subjects more abstract and difficult to understand than those examined in the Physics.
3.
The fundamental question of Aristotle’s metaphysics, and therefore of metaphysics as a subject, is What is the nature of being? However, this question was asked before Aristotle, so he was not the first metaphysician.
In addition, it has admitted a variety of interpretations over the centuries, though for most philosophers it does not include such subjects as astral projection, UFOs, or psychic surgery.
4.
The first Western philosophers are known
collectively as the pre-Socratics, a loose chronological term applying to those Greek philosophers who lived before Socrates (c. 470–399 B.C.).
5.
The thinking of
these early philosophers ushered in a perspective that made possible a deep understanding of the natural world. Advanced civilization is the direct consequence of the Greek discovery of mathematics and the Greek invention of philosophy.
The Milesians
6.
Thales conceived and looked for (and is said to be the first to do so) a basic stuff out of which all is constituted. He pronounced it to be water.
7.
Thales also introduced a perspective that was
not mythological in character. His view contributed
to the idea that nature runs itself according
to fixed processes that govern underlying substances.
8. Anaximander thought the basic substance must be more elementary
than water and
must be ageless, boundless, and indeterminate.
9.
Anaximenes
pronounced the basic substance to be air.
Pythagoras
10. Pythagoras
is said to have maintained that things are numbers, but, more accurately (according to his wife Theano), Pythagoras meant that things are things because they can be enumerated. If something
can be counted, it is a thing
(whether physical or
not).
11. For Pythagoras, there is an intimacy between things and numbers. Things participate in the universe of order and harmony. This led to the concept that fundamental reality is eternal, unchanging, and accessible only to reason.
Heraclitus and Parmenides
12. For Heraclitus, the essential feature of reality is fire, whose nature is ceaseless change determined by a cosmic order he called the logos,
through which there is a harmonious union of opposites. Such ceaseless change raises the problem
of identity (can I step into the same river twice?) and the problem of personal identity (am I the same person over a lifetime?)
13. Parmenides deduced from a priori principles that being is a changeless, single, permanent, indivisible, and undifferentiated whole. Motion and generation are impossible, for if being itself were to change it would become something different. But what is different from being is non- being, and non-being just plain isn’t.
Empedocles and Anaxagoras
14. Empedocles,
reconciling the
views of Heraclitus and Parmenides, recognized change in objects but said they were composed of changeless basic material particles: earth, air, fire, water. The apparent changes in the objects of experience were in reality changes in the positions of the basic particles. He also recognized basic forces of change, love, and strife.
15. Anaxagoras introduced philosophy to Athens and introduced into
metaphysics the distinction between matter and mind. He held that the formation of the world resulted from rotary motion induced in mass by mind = reason = nous.
16. Mind did not create matter, but only acted on it,
and did not act out of purpose or objective.
Unlike Empedocles, Anaxagoras believed matter was composed of particles that were infinitely divisible.
The Atomists
17. Leucippus and Democritus: All things are composed of minute, imperceptible, indestructible, indivisible, eternal, and uncreated particles, differing in size, shape, and perhaps weight. Atoms are infinite in number and eternally in motion.
18. The Atomists distinguished inherent
and
noninherent qualities
of everyday objects: color and taste are not really “in” objects, but other qualities, such as weight and hardness, are.
19. The Atomists held that because things move, empty space must be real.
20. The Atomists were determinists. They believed that atoms operate in strict accordance with physical laws. They said future motions would be completely predictable for anyone with enough knowledge about the shapes, sizes, locations, directions, and velocities of the atoms.
21. The common thread of the pre-Socratics: all believed that the world we experience is merely a manifestation of a more fundamental, underlying reality.
The Nature of Being?
(Some of the various questions a philosopher might have in mind when he or she asks the question)
Profile: Pythagoras
(Remembered for the Pythagorean Theorem, actually discovered earlier by the Babylonians)
On Rabbits and Motion
(Two of Zeno’s antimotion arguments explained)
Mythology
(The legacy of ancient myths)
6. A note on
Parmenides and
the
Atomists.
For Parmenides, the only alternative to being was non-being (nonexistence), so that if
being itself could undergo change of any kind (that is, could be different in some way from what it was originally), the only way for being to be different would be for it not to exist.
But that is logically absurd, for being cannot be and not-be at the
same time. Thus, it is impossible for being to change.
The Atomists used the idea of a “void” (the Greek word is kenon, the Latin word vacuum)
to give “room” for things (atoms) to undergo change. But empty space was also real.
A helpful way to understand this is to note that
while the void was “nothing”
(no-thing), it
was
not non-being. So for the Atomists
both
things and no-things
existed: both had being (as opposed to non-being). A comparison of the two views appears below.
Parmenides and the Atomists Compared
Parmenides
|
|
BEING IS
|
NON-BEING IS NOT
|
Atomists
|
|
BEING
Thing (Body)
No-Thing (Void) IS
|
NON-BEING IS NOT
|
Source: Unknown
8. “The behavior of atoms is governed entirely by physical laws.” “Humans have free will.” Are these statements incompatible?
Explain.
We don’t believe they ever invented
a beginning philosophy student who doubted free will. So regardless of your own
views on the subject, it can’t hurt
to argue against the idea. If it
does nothing else, it will help students to see that the idea that
we
have free will is
not the self-evident thing that it seems. Chapter 17 discusses the problem of
Free Will in depth, so you may want to postpone detailed discussion until then.
A good way to begin is by stipulating that Smith has free will if and only if it was physically possible for her to have acted differently in the same circumstances. Hence: If she has free will then it was physically possible for the atoms in the parts of her body that moved when she acted to have moved differently in the same circumstances. And if the atoms could have moved differently in the same circumstances, then they are not governed by physical laws. So, if they are governed, then she doesn’t have free will.
Possibly someone will ask, and even if nobody does ask the subject should be brought up anyway, why it is that, if it were possible for something physical to have behaved differently in the same circumstances, then it was not governed by physical law. The answer is that that’s what it is to be governed by physical law. Take a simple law, for example, water boils at 100 degrees Celsius. What it means to say
that that is a
law
is that if you raise the temperature
of some water to 100 degrees it will boil. If you could raise the water to 100 degrees without its boiling, then it wouldn’t be a law that water boils at that temperature.
A rejoinder might be—and few students will raise it, though you might—that it is consistent with the idea that the activity of subatomic entities is governed by physical laws that there are “uncaused events” in the subatomic realm, and that
therefore a subatomic entity could have behaved differently in exactly the same circumstances even though it is governed by physical laws. It might then further be suggested
that
if subatomic entities could
have behaved differently
in
the same circumstances while being governed by physical laws, then so could atoms and larger things, such as Smith’s arms and legs, since subatomic entities exist in these atoms and larger things.
However, let’s set aside the scientific controversies involved in this rejoinder and suppose that the atoms in Smith’s arms, while being governed by physical laws, could have moved differently due to the “uncaused” activity of internal subatomic
entities. The point is, so what? True, it
would follow that Smith has free will, as defined above, for she could have acted differently in the same circumstances (at least her body parts could have moved differently). But if she had acted differently, it would have been due to the “uncaused activity” of subatomic particles within her body, and
not
due to her.
This is a
good place to bring forth the old dilemma: Either your act
was
caused, or it wasn’t. If it was, then it couldn’t have not happened. And if it wasn’t, then you didn’t cause it. Either way, you can’t be held to account for your act.
Thales (c. 640–546 B.C.)
Anaximander (c. 610–547 B.C.)
On the Nature
of
Things
Anaximenes (fl. c. 545 B.C.)
Pythagoras (c. 580–500 B.C.)
Theano of Croton (sixth century B.C.)
On Piety
Heraclitus (c. 535–475 B.C.)
Parmenides (fifth century B.C.)
Zeno (c. 489–430 B.C.)
Empedocles (c. 490–430 B.C.)
On the Nature of Things
Purifications
Anaxagras (c. 500–428 B.C.)
Democritus (460–370 B.C.)
Little World System
On Nature
In the Nature of Man
Leucippus (mid-fifth century B.C.)
On Mind
No comments:
Post a Comment